OK, I may be guilty of a DoS attack attempt on mathematicians' brains here, so lest anyone waste too much precious brain time decoding this deliberately cryptic statement, let me do it for you. •1/15

First, as some asked, it is to be parenthesized as: “∀x.∀y.((∀z.((z∈x) ⇒ (((∀t.((t∈x) ⇒ ((t∈z) ⇒ (t∈y))))) ⇒ (z∈y)))) ⇒ (∀z.((z∈x) ⇒ (z∈y))))” (the convention is that ‘⇒’ is right-associative: “P⇒Q⇒R” means “P⇒(Q⇒R)”), but this doesn't clarify much. •2/15
Maybe we can make it a tad less abstruse by using guarded quantifiers (“∀u∈x.(…)” stands for “∀u.((u∈x)⇒(…))”): it is then “∀x.∀y.((∀z∈x.(((∀t∈x.((t∈z) ⇒ (t∈y)))) ⇒ (z∈y))) ⇒ (∀z∈x.(z∈y)))”. •3/15
Maybe a tad clearer again by writing “P(u)” for “u∈y” and leaving out the quantifier on y, viꝫ: “∀x.((∀z∈x.(((∀t∈x.((t∈z) ⇒ P(t)))) ⇒ P(z))) ⇒ (∀z∈x.P(z)))” [✯]. Now it appears as an induction principle: namely, … •4/15
… “in order to prove P(z) for all z∈x, we can assume, when proving P(z), that P(t) is already known for all t∈z∩x” (n.b.: “(∀z.(Q(z)⇒P(z)))⇒(∀z.P(z))” can be read “in order to prove P(z) for all z, we can assume Q(z) known when proving P(z)”). •5/15
This is a principle known as “∈-induction”: it is perhaps clearer when not guarded by x, “((∀z.(((∀t.((t∈z) ⇒ P(t)))) ⇒ P(z))) ⇒ (∀z.P(z)))” [✵], viꝫ “in order to prove P(z) for all z, we can assume, when proving P(z), that P(t) is already known for all t∈z”, … •6/15
… but of course the guarded version [✯] can be deduced from the unguarded [✵] by applying it to (z∈x)⇒P(z) in lieu of P(z). This is a particular case of “well-founded induction”, and the crucial point is that the “∈” relation on sets is indeed well-founded: … •7/15
… this follows (classically) from the axiom of Regularity, one of whose formulations is “∀v.((v≠∅) ⇒ (∃z∈v.(z∩v=∅))))” (“every set v has an element z which is disjoint from it”), or equivalently, “∀v.((∀z∈v.(z∩v≠∅))) ⇒ (v=∅))”: … •8/15
… from this we can easily deduce [✯] above by applying the axiom to v := {z∈x | ¬P(x)}, giving “∀x.((∀z∈x.(¬P(z) ⇒ ∃t∈x.((t∈z)∧¬P(t))))) ⇒ (¬∃z∈x.¬P(z)))” or, after a easy logical manipulations (taking contrapositives and moving negations around), … •9/15
… “∀x.((∀z∈x.(((∀t∈x.((t∈z) ⇒ P(t)))) ⇒ P(z))) ⇒ (∀z∈x.P(z)))” as claimed (and, as explained earlier, the original statement then follows by applying this to “z∈y” in lieu of P(z), or, if we prefer, v := x∖y in the axiom of Regularity). •10/15
(Actually, the unguarded statement “((∀z.(((∀t.((t∈z) ⇒ P(t)))) ⇒ P(z))) ⇒ (∀z.P(z)))” [✵] also follows, but there is a little more work here, essentially constructing the transitive closure, requiring a more set-theoretic power than I have used hitherto. … •11/15
… Conversely, this statement [✵] easily implies the axiom of Regularity by applying it to “z∉v” in lieu of P(z). So all are, in fact, equivalent over a reasonable set theory in classical logic. … •12/15
… But when working in intuitionistic logic it is more reasonable to work with induction principles such as [✵], which don't require moving negations around. Anyway, even classically, Regularity is mostly used for ∈-induction.) •13/15
So anyway, my original statement, “∀x.∀y.((∀z.((z∈x) ⇒ ((∀t.((t∈x) ⇒ (t∈z) ⇒ (t∈y)))) ⇒ (z∈y))) ⇒ (∀z.((z∈x) ⇒ (z∈y))))” was essentially a (perhaps better) rephrasing of the axiom of Regularity (and equivalent to it over the rest of ZF). •14/15
It's a bit recondite, but I think, as a formula, it has a certain gnomic beauty to it — almost poetry, I might say: this is the reason I left “∀z.((z∈x) ⇒ (z∈y)))” as such and not as “x⊆y”: it would spoil the rhyme. 🧐 •15/15

More from Maths

It is trying when mathematicians declare condescendingly that there is no point doing things because their models tell them so. Well maybe some of the assumptions don't hold up. How did that work out for the no additional risk from large events and no point in border controls...


During wave 1 cases fell very fast, faster than I think most people were expecting. Particularly in Scotland. Rt was probably ~0.5 until we started easing off.

This was despite a constant leak of cases coming out of hospitals and LTC facilities as we were rationing PPE and are policies were nowhere near ideal. There was insistence from infection control that droplet protections were sufficient. We have all learned a lot since then.

Not to mention we have learned to avoid the shit show of actively importing cases into care homes. We've learned not to repeat that. Other sectors have learned too.

We've learned a lot and there's no reason we can't control this new variant. But we will not manage if we don't try and act with clarity of purpose.

You May Also Like

One of the most successful stock trader with special focus on cash stocks and who has a very creative mind to look out for opportunities in dark times

Covering one of the most unique set ups: Extended moves & Reversal plays

Time for a 🧵 to learn the above from @iManasArora

What qualifies for an extended move?

30-40% move in just 5-6 days is one example of extended move

How Manas used this info to book


Post that the plight of the


Example 2: Booking profits when the stock is extended from 10WMA

10WMA =


Another hack to identify extended move in a stock:

Too many green days!

Read